"

4 Utilitarianism

chapter_four_utilitarianism

Maximize the good

In this chapter, we are going to build off the foundation of hedonism. Likewise, we will set aside the issues raised by Nozick’s experience machine (though that thought experiment is still relevant). One thing that may have struck you about the kind of hedonism that we just looked at was that it didn’t have much to say regarding what moral obligations you owe me, and what obligations I owe you. Hedonism is primarily focused on what is good for the individual, but not so much on what is good for the group. The theory to be explored in this chapter seeks to change that.

The theory for this chapter is called Utilitarianism. While that may sound like an odd word, it helps to focus on the first part of the word: utility. The utilitarian is focused on maximizing that which has utility. Utility can be understood as something like “usefulness” (utilitas in Latin means usefulness or advantage). Utilitarians are hedonists, and so they think that what is most useful to us is happiness. But, whereas the hedonist focuses solely on the individual’s happiness, the utilitarians is focused on maximizing happiness for as many people as is possible. You can think of it in the following way: the hedonist focuses on the individual, and the utilitarian focuses on the world.

How do they justify this? Well, the utilitarian thinks that the hedonist thesis is not all that there is to morality. Hedonism tells us what is good, but it does not necessarily tell us what to do with that fact. The utilitarian introduces a maximizing principle:

Maximizing Principle: An action is right if and only if it produces the best proportion of good-to-bad compared to available alternatives.

Since utilitarians are hedonists who embrace this principle, we can now define utilitarianism.

Utilitarianism:

the moral view that an action is right if creates the the best proportion of happiness to pain for the most amount of people possible, and wrong if it creates the wrong proportion

 

The utilitarian, therefore, is not just focused on individual happiness. A good action, according the utilitarian, is one that benefits as many as is possible. Almost no action that we can take, however, will produce only happiness. That is why the utilitarian focuses on the right proportion of happiness to pain. The benefit of this is that it gives us a moral decision making procedure. When you have to choose between two or more options, then you should choose the option which produces the best proportion of happiness to pain. The utilitarians calls this option optimific.

Optimific:

an action or policy that produces the greatest balance of benefits over drawbacks, resulting in the best overall outcome

Our first reading is from the English philosophy John Stuart Mill. Mill was a profound author and thinker. He wrote on mathematics, politics, language, history, science and was the author of his own encyclopedia. In the reading we are looking it, entitled Utilitarianism, we will see Mill’s arguments both that happiness is the only thing worth desiring, but also that morality is about doing the best for the most. Pay special attention to Mill’s “proof” in this reading. It is quite controversial.

In our second reading, we will focus more deeply on the trolly problems from chapter two. Judith Jarvis Thomson is our author here, and as we’ll see, she is quite adept when it comes to utilizing thought experiments. Thomson will argue that certain variations on the classic trolly problem will show that there is something wrong with the utilitarian’s focus on maximizing happiness.

Reading 1: John Stuart Mill – Utilitarianism (excerpts)

Handout:

The Problem: Can Morality Be Based on Happiness Alone?

Mill’s central philosophical concern is justifying the Greatest Happiness Principle (GHP)—the claim that actions are right insofar as they promote happiness, wrong as they produce the reverse. He inherits this view from Bentham, but he aims to refine it in response to powerful objections:

  • Is pleasure really the only thing desirable as an end?
  • Do some pleasures have more value than others?
  • Does utilitarianism demand too much from moral agents?
  • Can it explain the value of virtue, justice, and sacrifice?

Mill’s project is to answer these criticisms and defend utilitarianism as a comprehensive moral theory.

Mill’s Core Argument: The Greatest Happiness Principle

“The creed which accepts as the foundation of morals Utility, or the Greatest Happiness Principle, holds that actions are right in proportion as they tend to promote happiness…”

What is happiness?

For Mill, it means pleasure and the absence of pain. But unlike Bentham, he does not treat all pleasures as equal in value.

Key Innovations in Mill’s Utilitarianism

1. Qualitative Hedonism

Mill argues that some pleasures are higher than others—not just more intense or longer-lasting, but better in kind.

  • Pleasures that engage the higher faculties (e.g., intellect, imagination, moral sentiments) are superior.
  • He uses a famous comparison:

    “It is better to be a human being dissatisfied than a pig satisfied; better to be Socrates dissatisfied than a fool satisfied”.

  • Those “competently acquainted” with both types of pleasure invariably prefer the higher, even if they come with more suffering.

Takeaway: Mill introduces a normative hierarchy of pleasures, challenging Bentham’s purely quantitative approach.

2. Distinction Between Agent’s Happiness and General Happiness

Mill clarifies that utilitarian morality is not about maximizing one’s own happiness, but the happiness of all.

“As between his own happiness and that of others, utilitarianism requires him to be as strictly impartial as a disinterested and benevolent spectator”.

This aspect makes Mill’s utilitarianism altruistic and universalist, echoing the “golden rule” of morality.

3. Defense of Self-Sacrifice and Virtue

Mill accepts that people can—and should—sacrifice their own happiness, but only when this benefits others.

  • Self-renunciation is instrumentally good, not intrinsically:

    “A sacrifice which does not increase… the sum total of happiness… is wasted”.

He also addresses virtue:

  • People often value virtue (or truth, freedom, etc.) for their own sake.
  • Mill argues this does not refute utilitarianism: these values are “parts of happiness”, internalized through psychological association.

Mill’s Responses to Major Objections

Objection 1: Utilitarianism is a “doctrine fit for swine”

Response: Only if one assumes all pleasures are base. Mill insists human pleasures (e.g., reading, friendship, creativity) are of a higher nature than bodily gratification.

Objection 2: Humans can’t be happy

Response: Mill distinguishes sustainable happiness (tranquility and excitement in balance) from rapture. He argues that happiness is attainable and that social reform can expand access to it.

Objection 3: Utilitarianism is too demanding

Response: Mill separates the standard of rightness from motive. People need not always act from utility, but their actions should conform to it. Most right actions serve private, not public, utility.

Objection 4: Utility is “mere expediency”

Response: Mill distinguishes true utility from short-term expediency. Lying might be expedient now, but undermines long-term trust—thus failing the utility test.

Mill’s “Proof” of the Principle of Utility (Chapter 4)

Mill acknowledges that first principles of ethics can’t be “proven” in the ordinary sense. His strategy is analogical:

  • Just as visible things are those we see, desirable things are those we actually desire.
  • People desire happiness; thus, it is desirable.
  • And since people also desire virtue, money, etc., these are desirable as parts of happiness, not independent goods.

This is often called a naturalistic fallacy, but it forms the core of Mill’s empirical ethics.


Reading 2: Judith Jarvis Thomson – The Trolley Problem

 

The Problem: Why Is It Permissible to Kill One to Save Five Sometimes, But Not Others?

Judith Jarvis Thomson revisits a moral puzzle first introduced by Philippa Foot. At the center of this puzzle is a contrast:

  • Case 1 – Trolley Driver: You are driving a trolley headed toward five people. You can divert it onto another track, where it will kill one. Most people say this is permissible.
  • Case 2 – Transplant: A surgeon can save five patients by killing a healthy person and distributing his organs. Most people say this is not permissible.

The challenge: Why is it morally permissible to kill one to save five in Trolley Driver but not in Transplant? Both involve sacrificing one to save five, yet our intuitions diverge.

This puzzle—why do our moral intuitions distinguish these cases?—is what Thomson calls The Trolley Problem.

Thomson’s Goal and Method

Thomson’s goal is not merely to describe intuitions, but to find a principled explanation that tracks them. She critiques and expands on Philippa Foot’s original solution, using an analytic method: constructing variations of the cases to isolate morally relevant features.

I–II. The Setup and Foot’s View

  • Foot distinguishes between killing and letting die, arguing that killing is worse. Therefore, in Transplant, the surgeon would be killing, which is worse than letting die in Trolley Driver.
  • Thomson accepts this distinction, initially—but begins to question whether it explains our judgments adequately.

III. Bystander at the Switch

A new case:

  • You are not the driver, but a bystander with access to a switch. If you do nothing, five will die. If you flip the switch, one will die.
  • Most still say it’s permissible to flip the switch.

Thomson argues that this undermines Foot’s thesis: the bystander is not already involved in the harm (unlike the driver), yet may still act. So the distinction between killing and letting die can’t do all the work.

IV. Using as a Means

She explores Kantian ideas: it’s wrong to treat people as mere means. In Transplant, the healthy man is used to save others. But in Bystander, the one person is not used as a means—his death is a side-effect, not a tool.

Proposed test: Would the plan to save the five work if the one person disappeared? If yes, the one is not used as a means.

  • In Transplant: if the healthy man disappears, the plan fails → he is used as a means.
  • In Bystander: the plan still works → the one is not used as a means.

But complications arise: Loop variants of the trolley case show the one is needed to stop the trolley. So perhaps the “means” test is insufficient.

V–VII. The Distributive Principle and Rights

Thomson introduces two new principles:

  1. Distributive Principle: It’s sometimes permissible to redirect an existing threat from many to fewer, as long as you don’t use impermissible means.
  2. Rights-Based Constraint: You cannot infringe someone’s stringent rights (e.g., bodily integrity) to save others.

“It is not morally required that we let a burden fall on five if we can redirect it onto one—unless doing so would infringe that one’s rights.”

This explains:

  • Why Bystander is permissible: the redirection doesn’t violate stringent rights.
  • Why Transplant and Fat Man are not: they involve direct, intentional infringement of bodily rights.

VIII. Degree of Rights Infringement

Thomson also introduces a spectrum of rights:

  • Some rights are trivial (e.g., property rights).
  • Others are stringent (e.g., the right not to be killed).

She uses variants where the bystander must:

  • Cross the one person’s property (trivial right): many say this is permissible.
  • Push a fat man off a bridge (stringent right): clearly impermissible.

Implication: permissibility depends not just on numbers saved, but the kind of right being infringed.

IX–X. Limitations and Implications

Thomson emphasizes moral ambiguity: some cases resist clear-cut answers because the concepts of “threat,” “means,” and “rights” involve degrees and context.

  • Moral intuition is sensitive to these subtleties, even if our theories are not.
  • She resists pure consequentialism, insisting that certain actions are morally impermissible even when they maximize lives saved.

 

Media Attributions

  • image6
definition

License

Ethics: A New Introduction Copyright © by Kevin Patton. All Rights Reserved.

Share This Book